Dictionary Definition
altruism n : the quality of unselfish concern for
the welfare of others [syn: selflessness] [ant:
egoism]
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Noun
- Regard for others, both natural and moral; devotion to the interests of others; brotherly kindness; -- opposed to egoism or selfishness.
Synonyms
- philanthropy
- selflessness
- someone to bell the cat
Antonyms
- misanthropy (hatred of human race)
- egoism
Translations
- Croatian: altruizam
- Portuguese: altruísmo
- German: Altruismus
- Swedish: altruism
See also
- altruist
- altruistic
- misandry (hatred of males)
- misogyny (hatred of females)
Swedish
Noun
altruismRelated terms
Extensive Definition
Altruism is selfless concern for the welfare
of others. It is a traditional virtue in many cultures, and
central to many religious traditions. This idea was often described
as the Golden
rule of ethics. Altruism is the opposite of selfishness.
Altruism can be distinguished from a feeling of
loyalty and duty. Altruism focuses on a
motivation to help others or a want to do good
without reward, while duty focuses on a moral obligation towards a
specific individual (for example, God, a king), a specific organization
(for example, a government), or an abstract
concept (for example, patriotism etc). Some
individuals may feel both altruism and duty, while others may not.
Pure altruism is giving without regard to reward or the benefits of
recognition.
The concept has a long history in philosophical and ethical thought, and has more
recently become a topic for psychologists (especially
evolutionary
psychology researchers), sociologists, evolutionary
biologists, and ethologists. While ideas about
altruism from one field can have an impact on the other fields, the
different methods and focuses of these fields lead to different
perspectives on altruism. Researches on altruism were sparked in
particular after the murder of Kitty
Genovese in 1964, who was stabbed during half an hour, with
passive witnesses withholding themselves from helping her.
Altruism in social sciences
If one performs an act beneficial to others with a view to gaining some personal benefit, then it isn't an altruistically motivated act. There are several different perspectives on how "benefit" (or "interest") should be defined. A material gain (for example, money, a physical reward, etc.) is clearly a form of benefit, while others identify and include both material and immaterial gains (affection, respect, happiness, satisfaction etc.) as being philosophically identical benefits.According to psychological
egoism, while people can exhibit altruistic behavior, they
cannot have altruistic motivations. Psychological egoists would say
that while they might very well spend their lives benefitting
others with no material benefit (or a material net loss) to
themselves, their most basic motive for doing so is always to
further their own
interests. For example, it would be alleged that the
foundational motive behind a person acting this way is to advance
their own psychological well-being ("good feelings").
The problem (known in philosophy as the "problem
of love") arises from an analysis of the human will and
is often debated among Thomistic
philosophers. The problem centers on Thomas
Aquinas's understanding that human expressions of love are
always based partly on love of self and similitude of being: “Even
when a man loves in another what he loves not in himself, there is
a certain likeness of proportion: because as the latter is to that
which is loved in him, so is the former to that which he loves in
himself.”
The French philosopher Pierre
Rousselot (1878-1915) located the philosophical problem in
terms of a pure "ecstatic" or totally selfless love versus an
egotistic, more self-interested love, beginning his examination
from Aristotle's text (Nicomachean
Ethics, Book 9): "The friendly feelings that we bear for
another have arisen from the friendly feelings that we bear for
ourselves".
Relations between altruist acts and self-interest
were a common problem among French 17th century moralists, examined
in particular by
La Rochefoucauld, as well as Jansenists such
as Pascal and
Nicole.
These authors claimed that all acts of generosity were in fact acts
of vanity, a stance later
supported by Mandeville. La
Rochefoucauld could thus write, in his first Maxim: "What we call
virtues are often just a collection of casual actions and selfish
interests which chance or our own industry manages to arrange [in a
certain way]. It is not always from valor that men are valiant, or
from chastity that women are chaste."
This classical theory, which gave rise to
rational
egoism, was harshly opposed by Adam Smith in
his
Theory Of Moral Sentiments:
"It is the great fallacy of Dr Mandeville's book
to represent every passion as wholly vicious, which is so in any
degree and in any direction. It is thus that he treats every thing
as vanity which has any reference either to what are, or to what
ought to be, the sentiments of others; and it is by means of this
sophistry that he establishes his favourite conclusion, that
private vices are public benefits."
Critics of this theory conflating altruism with
vanity and self-interest often reject it on the grounds that it's
non-falsifiable;
in other words, it is impossible to prove or disprove because
immaterial gains such as a "good feelings" cannot be measured or
proven to exist in all people performing altruistic acts.
Psychological egoism has also been accused of using circular
logic: "If a person willingly performs an act, that means he
derives personal enjoyment from it; therefore, people only perform
acts that give them personal enjoyment". This particular statement
is circular because its conclusion is identical to its hypothesis
(it assumes that people only perform acts that give them personal
enjoyment, and concludes that people only perform acts that give
them personal enjoyment).
In common parlance, altruism usually means
helping another person without expecting material reward from that
or other persons, although it may well entail the "internal"
benefit of a "good feeling," sense of satisfaction, self-esteem,
fulfillment of duty (whether imposed by a religion or ideology or
simply one's conscience), or the like. In this way one need not
speculate on the motives of the altruist in question.
Humans are not exclusively altruistic towards
family members, previous co-operators or potential future allies,
but can be altruistic towards people they don't know and will never
meet. For example, some humans donate to international charities
and volunteer their time to help society's less fortunate. It can
however be argued that an individual would contribute to a charity
to gain respect or stature within his/her own community.
Altruism and game theory
It may strain plausibility to claim that these
altruistic deeds are done in the hope of a return favor. Influenced
by the consequentialist
perspective of utilitarianism, the
game
theory analysis of this 'just in case' strategy, where the
principle would be 'always help everyone in case you need to pull
in a favor in return', is a decidedly non-optimal strategy, where
the net expenditure of effort is far greater than the net profit
when it occasionally pays off.
According to some , it is difficult to believe
that these behaviors are solely explained as indirect selfish
rationality, be it
conscious or unconscious. Mathematical formulations of kin
selection, along the lines of the prisoner's
dilemma, are helpful as far as they go; but what a
game-theoretic explanation glosses over is the fact that altruistic
behavior can be attributed to that apparently mysterious
phenomenon, the conscience. One recent
suggestion, proposed by the philosopher Daniel
Dennett, was initially developed when considering the problem
of so-called 'free riders' in the tragedy
of the commons, a larger-scale version of the prisoner's
dilemma.
In game theory terms, a free rider is an agent who
draws benefits from a cooperative society without contributing. In
a one-to-one situation, free riding can easily be discouraged by a
tit-for-tat
strategy. But in a larger-scale society, where contributions and
benefits are pooled and shared, they can be incredibly difficult to
shake off.
Cooperative agents interact with each other, each
contributing resources and each drawing on the common good. Now
imagine a rogue free rider, an
agent who draws a favor ("you scratch my back") and later refuses
to return it. The problem is that free riding is always going to be
beneficial to individuals at cost to society. How can well-behaved
cooperative agents avoid being cheated? Over many generations, one
obvious solution is for cooperators to evolve the ability to spot
potential free riders in advance and refuse to enter into
reciprocal arrangements with them. Then, the canonical free
rider response is to evolve a more convincing disguise, fooling cooperators
into cooperating after all. This can lead to an evolutionary
arms races, with ever-more-sophisticated disguises and
ever-more-sophisticated detectors.
In this evolutionary arms race, how best might
one convince comrades that one really is a genuine cooperator, not
a free rider in disguise? One answer is by actually making oneself
a genuine cooperator, by erecting psychological
barriers to breaking promises, and by advertising this fact to
everyone else. In other words, a good solution is for organisms to
evolve things that everyone knows will force them to be cooperators
- and to make it obvious that they've evolved these things.
According to this theory, evolution will thus produce organisms who
are sincerely moral and who wear their hearts on their sleeves; in
short, evolution will give rise to the phenomenon of
conscience.
This theory, combined with ideas of kin
selection and the one-to-one sharing of benefits, may explain
how a blind process can produce a genuinely non-cynical form of
altruism that gives rise to the human conscience.
Critics of such technical game theory analysis
point out that it appears to forget that human beings are rational
and emotional. To presume an analysis of human behavior without
including human rationale or emotion is necessarily unrealistically
narrow, and treats human beings as if they are mere machines,
sometimes called Homo
economicus. Another objection is that often people donate
anonymously, so that it is impossible to determine if they really
did the altruistic act (compare with Kant's affirmation
that since motive
determines the moral nature of an act, and that none can know for
sure which motive was behind an act, therefore it is impossible to
know if one single moral act ever existed).
Beginning with an understanding that rational
human beings benefit from living in a benign universe, logically it
follows that particular human beings may gain substantial emotional
satisfaction from acts which they perceive to make the world a
better place.
Altruism in morality and politics
Altruists may be divided in two broad groups : Those who believe altruism is a matter of personal choice (and therefore selfishness can and should be tolerated - ethical egoism even supports egoism as a moral stance, denying altruism any value), and those who believe that altruism is a moral ideal which should be embraced, if possible, by all human beings.A prominent example of the former branch of
altruist political thought is Lysander
Spooner, who, in Natural Law, writes: "''Man, no doubt, owes
many other moral duties to his fellow men; such as to feed the
hungry, clothe the naked, shelter the homeless, care for the sick,
protect the defenceless, assist the weak, and enlighten the
ignorant. But these are simply moral duties, of which each man must
be his own judge, in each particular case, as to whether, and how,
and how far, he can, or will, perform them.''"
Since Aristotle's
classical distinction of regimes made in Politics,
III, altruism is often held to be the kind of ethic that should
guide the actions of politicians and other people in positions of
power. Such people are usually expected to set their own interests
aside and serve the populace. When they do not, they may be
criticized as defaulting on what is believed to be an ethical
obligation to place the interests of others above their own.
Ayn Rand, the
founder of Objectivism,
argued that altruism is immoral because self-sacrifice is
fundamentally incompatible with the objective requirements of human
life. She defined sacrifice as the exchange of something of
superior value for something of inferior value. Rand argued that
the fundamental moral value to a living entity was that entity's
own life, whose survival and flourishing depends upon the
self-interested pursuit, not selfless renunciation, of values.
Without value achievement there would be no living entities. As the
universe follows consistent and absolute laws and living beings
must take certain actions in accordance with their biological
natures to survive, she argued, the moral code cannot be arbitrary
but must follow a rational framework.
Sacrifice according to Rand is the worst kind of
moral transgression as it fundamentally undermines the basic
principle of a living entity: the optimization toward something
better and not something worse. She argued that if altruism as an
expression of self-sacrifice were universally and consistently
applied, humankind would not remain in existence for long.
Altruism in ethology and evolutionary biology
In the science of ethology (the study of animal behavior), and more generally in the study of social evolution, altruism refers to behavior by an individual that increases the fitness of another individual while decreasing the fitness of the actor. Researchers on alleged altruist behaviours among animals have been ideologically opposed to the social darwinist concept of the "survival of the fittest", under the name of "survival of the nicest"—the latter being globally compatible, however, with darwinist' theory of evolution. Insistence on such cooperative behaviours between animals was first exposed by the Russian zoologist and anarchist Peter Kropotkin in his 1902 book, Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution.Recent developments in game theory
(look into ultimatum
game) have provided some explanations for apparent altruism, as
have traditional evolutionary analyses. Among the proposed
mechanisms are:
- Behavioural manipulation (for example, by certain parasites that can alter the behavior of the host)
- Bounded rationality (for example, Herbert Simon)
- Conscience
- Kin selection including eusociality (see also "selfish gene")
- Memes (by influencing behavior to favour their own spread, for example, religion)
- Reciprocal altruism, mutual aid
- Selective investment theory - a theoretical proposal for the evolution of long-term, high-cost altruism
- Sexual selection, in particular, the Handicap principle
-
Reciprocity (social psychology)
- Indirect reciprocity (for example, reputation)
- Strong reciprocity
- Pseudo-reciprocity
The study of altruism was the initial impetus
behind George R.
Price's development of the Price
equation which is a mathematical equation used to study genetic
evolution. An interesting example of altruism is found in the
cellular slime moulds,
such as Dictyostelium
mucoroides. These protists live as individual amoebae until starved, at which
point they aggregate and form a multicellular fruiting body in
which some cells sacrifice themselves to promote the survival of
other cells in the fruiting body. Social behavior and altruism
share many similarities to the interactions between the many parts
(cells, genes) of an organism, but are distinguished by the ability
of each individual to reproduce indefinitely without an absolute
requirement for its neighbors.
Jorge Moll and Jordan Grafman, neuroscientists at
the
National Institutes of Health and LABS-D'Or Hospital Network
(J.M.) provided the first evidence for the neural bases of
altruistic giving in normal healthy volunteers, using
functional magnetic resonance imaging. In their research,
published in the
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA in October,
2006, they showed that both pure monetary rewards and charitable
donations activated the mesolimbic
reward pathway, a primitive part of the brain that usually lights
up in response to food and sex. However, when volunteers generously
placed their interests of others before their own by making
charitable donations, another brain circuit was selectively
activated: the subgenual cortex/septal region. These structures are
intimately related to social attachment and bonding in other
species. Altruism, the experiment suggested, was not a superior
moral faculty that suppresses basic selfish urges but rather was
basic to the brain, hard-wired and pleasurable.
A new study by Samuel
Bowles at the Santa Fe
Institute in New Mexico,
US, is seen by some as breathing new life into the model of
group
selection for Altruism, known as "Survival of the nicest".
Bowles conducted a genetic analysis of contemporary foraging
groups, including Australian
aboriginals, native Siberian Inuit populations and
indigenous tribal groups in Africa. It was found that hunter-gatherer
bands of up to 30 individuals were considerably more closely
related than was previously thought. Under these conditions,
thought to be similar to those of the middle and upper Paleolithic,
altruism towards other group-members would improve the overall
fitness of the group.
If an individual defended the group but was
killed, any genes that the individual shared with the overall group
would still be passed on. Early customs such as food sharing or
monogamy could have
levelled out the “cost” of altruistic behaviour, in the same way
that income taxes redistribute income in society. He assembled
genetic, climactic, archaeological, ethnographic and experimental
data to examine the cost-benefit relationship of human cooperation
in ancient populations. In his model, members of a group bearing
genes for altruistic behaviour pay a "tax" by limiting their
reproductive opportunities to benefit from sharing food and
information, thereby increasing the average fitness of the group as
well as their inter-relatedness. Bands of altruistic humans would
then act together to gain resources from other groups at this
challenging time in history..
Altruist theories in evolutionary biology were
contested by Amotz
Zahavi, the inventor of the signal theory and its correlative,
the handicap
principle, based mainly on his observations of the Arabian
Babbler, a bird commonly known for its surprising (alleged)
altruistic behaviours.
Altruism and religion
Most, if not all, of the world's religions promote altruism as a very important moral value. Christianity, Buddhism , and Sikhism place particular emphasis on altruistic morality, as noted above, but Judaism, Islam, Hinduism and many other religions also promote altruistic behavior. Altruism was central to the teachings of Jesus found in the Gospel especially in the Sermon on the Mount and the Sermon on the Plain. From biblical to medieval Christian traditions, tensions between self-affirmation and other-regard were sometimes discussed under the heading of "disinterested love," as in the Pauline phrase "love seeks not its own interests." In his book Indoctrination and Self-deception, Roderick Hindery tries to shed light on these tensions by contrasting them with impostors of authentic self-affirmation and altruism, by analysis of other-regard within creative individuation of the self, and by contrasting love for the few with love for the many. If love, which confirms others in their freedom, shuns propagandas and masks, assurance of its presence is ultimately confirmed not by mere declarations from others, but by each person's experience and practice from within. As in practical arts, the presence and meaning of love become validated and grasped not by words and reflections alone, but in the doing.Though it might seem obvious that altruism is
central to the teachings of Jesus, one important and influential
strand of Christianity would qualify this. St Thomas
Aquinas in the Summa
Theologica, I:II Quaestion 26, Article 4 states that we should
love ourselves more than our neighbour. His interpretation of the
Pauline phrase is that we should seek the common good more than the
private good but this is because the common good is a more
desirable good for the individual. 'You should love your neighbour
as yourself' from Leviticus 19 and
Matthew 22 is interpreted by St Thomas as meaning that love for
ourself is the exemplar of love for others. He does think though,
that we should love God more than ourselves and our neighbour,
taken as an entirety, more than our bodily life, since the ultimate
purpose of love of our neighbour is to share in eternal beatitude,
a more desirable thing than bodily well being. Comte was probably
opposing this Thomistic doctrine, now part of mainstream
Catholicism, in coining the word Altruism, as stated above.
Sikhism
Altruism is essential to the Sikh religion. In the late 1600s, Guru Gobind Singh Ji (the tenth guru in Sikhism), was in war with the Moghul rulers to protect the people of different faiths, when a fellow Sikh, Bhai Kanhaiya, attended the troops of the enemy. He gave water to the injured, which revived their strength. Some of them began to fight again and seemed to cause problems to the Sikh warriors. Sikh soldiers brought Bhai Kanhaiya before the Guru, and complained of his action that they considered counterproductive to their struggle on the battlefield. "What were you doing, and why?" asked the Guru. "I was giving water to the wounded because I saw your face in them," replied Bhai Kanhaiya. The Guru responded, "Then you should also give them ointment to heal their wounds. You were practicing what you were coached in the house of the Guru." In love of altruism, is there any room for hatred or duality?It was under the tutelage of the Guru that Bhai
Kanhaiya subsequently founded a volunteer corps for altruism. This
volunteer corps till to date is engaged in doing good to others and
trains new volunteering recruits for doing the same.
It is claimed by some Sikhs that Bhai Kanhaiya's
successors who continued the tradition of serving others and who
committed their lives to service of the sick and wounded lived
longer than usual life spans. Bhai Kanhaiya’s successors were not
related genetically in order to account for their exceptional
longevity. Rather they were volunteers from the Sikh organizations
who committed their lives to serve the sick; first they did it
themselves and then they recruited others to do the same. All of
them defied the recorded longevity norms of the time for a long
span of over three centuries.
Longevity is determined by many factors, freedom
from disease and stress are two such factors. The altruists were
certainly observed to live calm and tranquil lives. For Sikhs,
altruism was made an act of faith by their founders.
See also
Notes
References
- Oord, Thomas Jay (2007). The Altruism Reader: Selections from Writings on Love, Religion, and Science (Philadelphia: Templeton Foundation Press).
- Batson, C.D. (1991). The altruism question. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
- Fehr, E. & Fischbacher, U. (23 October 2003). The nature of human altruism. In Nature, 425, 785 – 791.
- Comte, Auguste, Catechisme positiviste (1852) or Catechism of Positivism, tr. R. Congreve, (London: Kegan Paul, 1891)
- Kropotkin, Peter, Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution (1902)
- Thomas Jay Oord, Science of Love (Philadelphia: Templeton Foundation Press, 2004).
- Nietzsche, Friedrich, Beyond Good and Evil
- Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, The Philosophy of Poverty (1847)
- Lysander Spooner, Natural Law
- Matt Ridley, The Origins of Virtue
- Oliner, Samuel P. and Pearl M. Towards a Caring Society: Ideas into Action. West Port, CT: Praeger, 1995.
- The Evolution of Cooperation, Robert Axelrod, Basic Books, ISBN 0-465-02121-2
- The Selfish Gene, Richard Dawkins (1990), second edition -- includes two chapters about the evolution of cooperation, ISBN 0-19-286092-5
- Robert Wright, The moral animal, Vintage, 1995, ISBN 0-679-76399-6.
- Madsen, E.A., Tunney, R., Fieldman, G., Plotkin, H.C., Dunbar, R.I.M., Richardson, J.M., & McFarland, D. (2006) Kinship and altruism: A cross-cultural experimental study. British Journal of Psychology
- Wedekind, C. and Milinski, M. Human Cooperation in the simultaneous and the alternating Prisoner's Dilemma: Pavlov versus Generous Tit-for-tat. Evolution'', Vol. 93, pp. 2686-2689, April 1996.
External links
- Society
- What is Altruism? from Altruists International
- The Sciences
- Altruism: Myth or Reality?
- Biological Altruism at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- The Altruistic Personality and Prosocial Behavior Institute at Humboldt State University
- Greater Good magazine examines the roots of Altruism at the University of California, Berkeley
- BBC Radio 4's In Our Time programme on Altruism (requires RealAudio)
altruism in Arabic: الإيثار
altruism in Bulgarian: Алтруизъм
altruism in Czech: Altruismus
altruism in Danish: Altruisme
altruism in German: Altruismus
altruism in Estonian: Altruism
altruism in Spanish: Altruísmo
altruism in French: Altruisme
altruism in Croatian: Altruizam
altruism in Indonesian: Altruisme
altruism in Italian: Altruismo
altruism in Hebrew: זולתנות
altruism in Lithuanian: Altruizmas
altruism in Hungarian: Altruizmus
altruism in Malay (macrolanguage):
Altruisme
altruism in Dutch: Altruïsme
altruism in Japanese: 奉仕
altruism in Norwegian: Altruisme
altruism in Norwegian Nynorsk: Altruisme
altruism in Polish: Altruizm
altruism in Portuguese: Altruísmo
altruism in Russian: Альтруизм
altruism in Slovak: Altruizmus
altruism in Slovenian: Altruizem
altruism in Serbian: Алтруизам
altruism in Finnish: Altruismi
altruism in Swedish: Altruism
altruism in Turkish: Diğerkâmlık
altruism in Ukrainian: Альтруїзм
altruism in Chinese: 利他主义
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
BOMFOG,
Benthamism, Christian
charity, Christian love, agape, beneficence, benevolence, benevolent
disposition, benevolentness, bigheartedness, brotherly
love, caritas, charitableness, charity, commitment, consecration, dedication, devotion, disinterest, disinterestedness,
do-goodism, flower power, generosity, giving, goodwill, grace, greatheartedness,
humaneness, humanitarianism,
humanity, humility, largeheartedness,
love, love of mankind,
modesty, philanthropism, philanthropy, sacrifice, self-abasement,
self-abnegation, self-denial, self-devotion, self-effacement,
self-forgetfulness, self-immolation, self-neglect,
self-neglectfulness, self-renouncement, self-sacrifice,
self-subjection, selflessness, unacquisitiveness,
unpossessiveness,
unselfishness,
utilitarianism,
welfarism,
well-disposedness